Skip to content

KHANNEA

She/Her – ☿ – Cosmist – Cosmicist – Succubus Fetishist – Transwoman – Lilithian – TechnoGaianist – Transhumanist – Living in de Pijp, Amsterdam – Left-Progressive – Kinkster – Troublemaker – 躺平 – Wu Wei. – Anti-Capitalist – Antifa Sympathizer – Boutique Narcotics Explorer – Salon Memeticist – Neo-Raver – Swinger – Alû Halfblood – Socialist Extropian – Coolhunter – TechnoProgressive – Singularitarian – Exochiphobe (phobic of small villages and countryside) – Upwinger – Dystopia Stylist – Cyber-Cosmicist – Slut (Libertine – Slaaneshi Prepper – Ordained Priestess of Kopimi. — 夢魔/魅魔 – Troublemaker – 躺平 – 摆烂 – 無爲 – Wu Wei – mastodon.social/@Khannea – google.com, pub-8480149151885685, DIRECT, f08c47fec0942fa0

Menu
  • – T H E – F A R – F R O N T I E R –
  • Alignments
  • Dancing with the Devil on Prednisone: A Cluster Headache Pre-Event Modulation Trial under Extreme Triggers
  • My Political Positions
  • Shaping the Edges of the Future
  • Some Of My Art
  • “Stop the Spiral” – My Official Conversion Therapy Councelling Service
Menu

2025 Revision — Ich bin ein Neo-Eugeneticist

Posted on May 1, 2025May 1, 2025 by Khannea Sun'Tzu

“To create well is not to possess, but to care for what comes after you.

True wisdom lies not in control, but in shaping with love what you cannot keep.”

— Inspired by Diotima of Mantinea

“I have known sex as worship, as escape, as weapon, as anesthesia.
But never as a reason to replicate myself.
Pleasure I welcome—inheritance, I refuse.”
– Khannea Sun’Tzu

Preface (2025)

This article was originally conceived in 2009 at a time when discussions around genetic engineering still hovered uneasily between speculative futurism and cultural taboo. My original article was clumsy. Back then, terms like CRISPR, polygenic scoring, and germline modification were either misunderstood or treated as academic curiosities—fascinating perhaps to bioethicists or Silicon Valley evangelists, but far removed from the public imagination or democratic discourse. That world has changed. Radically.

As we step into 2025, we find ourselves surrounded by technologies that, barely a decade ago, would have sounded like dystopian plot devices or utopian pipe dreams. CRISPR-Cas9 and its more precise successors have entered mainstream medical experimentation. Base editing is undergoing clinical trials for previously untreatable conditions. Polygenic risk scoring, once dismissed as too noisy for clinical relevance, is now routinely used in fertility clinics and personalized wellness regimes. Predictive behavioral genomics—though controversial—is being piloted in both public health policy and corporate hiring. Synthetic biology is no longer confined to lab-grown meat or microbes but has begun edging toward rewriting developmental pathways in multicellular organisms, including humans.

These are no longer tools of the future. They are here, now—imperfect, yes, but accelerating. We live in a moment where the code of life is becoming programmable, where the barrier between biology and design is dissolving. The implications are vast: medical, ethical, social, philosophical. What used to be hypothetical debates about “designer babies” or “genetic determinism” are now materializing in the form of policy decisions, consumer choices, and inequalities both anticipated and unanticipated.

This updated version of the article is not a retraction, nor an apology, but rather a deepening and widening of the original inquiry. The core ethical question—who gets to choose the bodies and minds of future generations?—has only grown more urgent. But the framing must also evolve. We must now ask: Who governs the genome? Who defines what is “healthy” or “normal”? Who gets access to these choices, and who is left behind? Can genetic freedom exist in a capitalist system, or will enhancement become the new class divide? Can liberal democracies develop regulatory models fast and robust enough to preserve human dignity without stifling scientific progress?

It is critical that we confront these questions not through moral panic or reactive legislation, but with a calm, scientifically grounded, and ethically rigorous commitment to transparency, equity, and justice. This requires that we resist both techno-utopian fantasies and technophobic paralysis. It demands an honest reckoning with history’s sins, but not a blanket rejection of future potential.

Above all, it requires the courage to imagine new ethical frameworks for a species that has, for better or worse, become capable of editing itself.

Let us proceed with clarity, humility, and a fierce devotion to the future of freedom.

“To abstain from care when care is possible is not virtue—

it is fear disguised as innocence. Love acts. Love intervenes.”
— Inspired by Diotima of Mantinea


“I take lovers, not lineage.

My pleasure rewrites me;

my womb is as inert as a gem, not a seedbed.”

— Khannea Sun’Tzu

 

The Ethics of Inaction: When Doing Nothing Is Abuse

In ethical debates on genetic intervention, the fiercest objections often arise from the fear of doing too much—of playing God, of overreaching, of turning children into designed commodities. But what about the moral burden of doing too little? What if the greater sin is not action, but inaction?

Take a simple, widely accepted medical example: vitamin K prophylaxis in newborns. Without this standard intervention, infants are at risk of vitamin K deficiency bleeding (VKDB)—a potentially fatal or brain-damaging condition that can manifest in the first weeks of life. Vitamin K doesn’t cure a disease; it prevents one. It doesn’t enhance—it stabilizes. It is a basic medical safeguard. And yet, when refused by parents—often for vague or conspiratorial reasons—children suffer irreparable harm. In multiple countries, including the Netherlands and the U.S., such refusal has been classified as medical neglect, and in rare cases, has triggered legal action (Shearer, M. J., 2009, Blood Reviews).

This is not a fringe case. It is an object lesson in the ethics of prevention. If withholding a vitamin known to prevent brain damage constitutes neglect, then by what logic would withholding a safe genetic or pharmaceutical intervention that prevents another predictable and debilitating outcome—say, inherited deafness, cystic fibrosis, or an early-onset neurological disorder—not be considered similarly abusive?

There is a double standard in our thinking. Interventions like folic acid, vitamin D, or K are seen as maternal responsibility. But propose a molecular-level intervention that achieves the same goal—safeguarding future health—and suddenly we wade into controversy. Yet from a moral standpoint, the distinction between nutritional prophylaxis and genomic correction is artificial. Both serve the same end: reducing avoidable suffering in people who cannot yet consent.

Failure to act, when safe, low-cost, and effective interventions are available, should not be treated as ethically neutral. It is not just a missed opportunity—it is a choice with consequences. If society is willing to acknowledge that allowing a child to suffer brain damage through vitamin K refusal is a form of neglect, then it must also have the moral courage to recognize new forms of neglect emerging from unjustified refusals of next-generation medical prevention.

Many afflictions in newborns or in utero absolutely require intervention to prevent lifelong disability or death. In fact, modern medicine is built on precisely this premise: that early, safe, timely interventions can protect or vastly improve a child’s life trajectory. Failing to act when these interventions are available is not just neglect—it can be catastrophic. Here’s a list of notable examples, grouped by type:

Nutritional Deficiency Conditions

▸ Vitamin K Deficiency Bleeding (VKDB)

  • Preventable with a single injection of vitamin K at birth.

  • Without it, infants are at risk of severe brain bleeds and death.

  • Non-intervention = high risk of irreversible disability or death.

▸ Neural Tube Defects (e.g., spina bifida, anencephaly)

  • Folic acid taken before and during early pregnancy drastically reduces risk.

  • Failure to supplement properly is linked to devastating neurological outcomes.

  • CDC: Folic Acid & Birth Defects

Metabolic and Genetic Disorders (Newborn Screening)

These are detected via newborn heel prick tests, with many treatable if caught early:

▸ Phenylketonuria (PKU)

  • Without intervention: severe intellectual disability.

  • With dietary modification from birth: normal development.

▸ Congenital Hypothyroidism

  • Without early thyroid hormone therapy: profound cognitive impairment.

  • Easily treatable with daily medication.

▸ Medium-chain acyl-CoA dehydrogenase deficiency (MCADD)

  • Undetected, can cause sudden death during fasting.

  • With early dietary management: normal life expectancy.

  • Source: ACMG ACT Sheets

Infectious Disease Protection

▸ Hepatitis B Vaccine at Birth

  • Protects infants from chronic hepatitis and future liver cancer.

  • Refusing vaccination leaves child vulnerable to lifelong infection.

▸ Antiretroviral Treatment in HIV+ Mothers

  • Without intervention: 15–45% transmission risk.

  • With treatment: <1% risk.

Congenital & Perinatal Conditions

▸ Hydrocephalus

  • Can be managed with a shunt.

  • Untreated: brain damage, blindness, early death.

▸ Cleft Palate

  • Surgical correction is standard and restores basic functions like eating and speaking.

  • Without it: severe disability and social exclusion.

Emerging Genomic Interventions

As polygenic risk scoring, gene therapy, and embryo screening evolve, the list grows:

▸ Spinal Muscular Atrophy (SMA)

  • Once fatal in early childhood.

  • Now treatable with Zolgensma, a one-time gene therapy (if given early enough).

▸ Beta-Thalassemia / Sickle Cell Anemia

  • Now candidates for CRISPR-based therapy.

  • Potentially curable if identified and treated soon enough.

  • Source: Frangoul et al., NEJM, 2021

Why This Matters Ethically

When intervention is available, safe, and effective, and inaction leads to harm, choosing not to intervene is ethically significant. These cases prove that:

  • Genetic conditions are not destiny.

  • Early actions can dramatically alter outcomes.

  • The line between “healing” and “enhancing” is blurry—but in many cases, clear preventive care is morally obvious.

Put simply: if we can safely prevent lifelong harm, then not doing so is not neutrality—it’s abandonment.

“The sad truth is that most evil is done by people who never make up their minds to be good or evil.”
— Hannah Arendt,
The Life of the Mind


The Ethical Terrain: From Horror to Hope

The ethical landscape of human genetic modification is complex and multifaceted, encompassing a range of perspectives and concerns. While the potential benefits of gene editing technologies like CRISPR are significant, they are accompanied by profound ethical considerations that society must address.​

Historical Context and Ethical Boundaries

The history of eugenics serves as a cautionary tale, illustrating how scientific advancements can be misused to justify coercive and discriminatory practices. The atrocities committed under the guise of improving the human race underscore the importance of establishing clear ethical boundaries. Modern discussions on gene editing emphasize the necessity of voluntary, informed, and democratically regulated applications of these technologies, ensuring that individual autonomy and human rights are upheld.​

Therapeutic vs. Enhancement Applications

Therapeutic applications of gene editing, aimed at correcting genetic disorders and preventing disease, are generally viewed as ethically permissible. However, the use of gene editing for enhancement purposes—such as increasing intelligence or physical abilities—raises significant ethical questions. Concerns include the potential for exacerbating social inequalities, the commodification of human traits, and the unforeseen consequences of altering complex genetic traits.​

Informed Consent and Intergenerational Implications

A critical ethical issue in germline editing is the inability of future generations to consent to genetic modifications that will affect them. This raises questions about the rights of individuals yet to be born and the responsibilities of current generations to consider the long-term implications of genetic interventions. Ensuring that gene editing practices do not infringe upon the autonomy and rights of future individuals is paramount.​

Equity and Access

The potential for gene editing technologies to widen existing social and economic disparities is a significant concern. If access to genetic enhancements is limited to those with financial means, it could lead to a society where advantages are biologically inherited, further entrenching inequality. Developing policies that promote equitable access to gene editing technologies is essential to prevent the emergence of a genetically stratified society.​AMA Journal of Ethics

Regulatory Frameworks and Global Governance

The rapid advancement of gene editing technologies necessitates the development of robust regulatory frameworks that can adapt to new scientific developments. International collaboration is crucial to establish guidelines that ensure the ethical application of gene editing, prevent misuse, and promote transparency. Engaging diverse stakeholders, including scientists, ethicists, policymakers, and the public, is vital in shaping policies that reflect a broad consensus on ethical standards.​

Conclusion

The promise of gene editing technologies is immense, offering the potential to alleviate suffering and improve human health. However, realizing these benefits requires careful ethical consideration, inclusive dialogue, and the establishment of equitable and transparent governance structures. By learning from history and engaging in proactive ethical deliberation, society can navigate the challenges posed by gene editing and harness its potential for the greater good.


“The liberties of none are safe unless the liberties of all are protected.”
— William O. Douglas, U.S. Supreme Court Justice

“We are no longer mysterious souls; we are now hackable animals.”
— Yuval Noah Harari, World Economic Forum, 2020

Clarifying the Terrain of Genetic Intervention

To meaningfully navigate the ethical and practical dimensions of human genetic modification, it is essential to clarify the three dominant categories of intervention that currently frame both public discourse and clinical practice. These approaches—while distinct in technical application and social consequence—are increasingly converging in terms of their implications for human health, autonomy, and intergenerational equity.

Somatic gene editing involves the targeted modification of a person’s DNA after conception. This form of therapy is designed primarily to treat or alleviate diseases at the level of specific tissues or cell lines, such as correcting defective genes in blood cells to treat sickle cell anemia or beta-thalassemia. Because these edits do not affect the reproductive cells (gametes), the changes are not inherited by offspring. They are, in essence, therapeutic interventions aimed at restoring function and mitigating suffering within the lifespan of a single individual. Clinical trials in this area have already shown promising outcomes, including the recent use of CRISPR-Cas9 in hematopoietic stem cells Frangoul et al., 2021, New England Journal of Medicine.

Germline genetic editing, on the other hand, alters the DNA in eggs, sperm, or embryos at a stage when the genetic changes can become heritable. These modifications, once introduced, are passed on to future generations and can reshape entire family lines. While this method holds enormous promise for eliminating certain inherited disorders—such as Huntington’s disease or Tay-Sachs—it also raises profound ethical concerns about long-term safety, informed consent (especially for future generations), and the risk of eugenic misuse. The 2018 case of He Jiankui’s CRISPR-edited embryos in China Lanphier et al., 2015, Nature serves as a widely cited example of premature and ethically reckless application of germline editing, sparking a global reckoning over bioethics and governance.

Embryo selection, often practiced in the context of in vitro fertilization (IVF), involves generating multiple embryos and then selecting which one(s) to implant based on genetic characteristics. While initially developed to avoid severe monogenic diseases such as cystic fibrosis or Tay-Sachs, embryo selection has rapidly evolved to include polygenic risk scoring—a statistical method that estimates the likelihood of complex traits such as heart disease, diabetes, or even cognitive ability based on the combined influence of many genes Karavani et al., 2019, Cell. This technique remains controversial, both because of its predictive limitations and the potential to drive parental selection preferences toward enhancement rather than prevention.

Despite their technical differences—somatic edits affecting only the individual, germline edits extending to descendants, and embryo selection relying on probabilistic screening rather than modification—these three approaches share a converging logic: they aim to reduce suffering, increase healthspan, and provide a form of biological agency that humanity has never previously possessed. Their ethical weight, therefore, cannot be judged solely by the molecular tools they employ. Instead, it must be assessed in light of their intent (healing or enhancing?), their scientific reliability, and the societal structures within which they are deployed.

As critics have pointed out, even benign interventions can lead to slippery slopes without adequate oversight Baylis, 2019, Journal of Medical Ethics. At the same time, to reject these interventions wholesale, on the basis of historic abuses or imagined futures, is to risk entrenching preventable suffering. Indeed, many scholars now argue for a model of precautionary pragmatism—accepting that genetic interventions are neither universally moral nor immoral, but conditional on transparency, safety, access, and consent Gyngell et al., 2021, Nature Reviews Genetics.

Thus, the central question is not merely what we can do, but why, for whom, and under what system of accountability. When science moves faster than governance—as it often does—it becomes imperative for both public and scholarly communities to participate in shaping ethical frameworks that reflect our collective values.


Key Peer-Reviewed Sources (Pro and Con Perspectives)

  • Frangoul, H. et al. (2021). CRISPR-Cas9 Gene Editing for Sickle Cell Disease and β-Thalassemia. New England Journal of Medicine. Link

  • Lanphier, E. et al. (2015). Don’t edit the human germ line. Nature, 519(7544), 410–411. Link

  • Baylis, F. (2019). Babies by design. Journal of Medical Ethics, 45(9), 563–566. Link

  • Gyngell, C., Bowman-Smart, H., & Savulescu, J. (2021). Moral reasons to edit the human genome. Nature Reviews Genetics, 22(12), 766–771. Link

  • Karavani, E. et al. (2019). Screening human embryos for polygenic traits has limited utility. Cell, 179(6), 1424–1435.e8. Link

  • Savulescu, J. (2001). Procreative Beneficence: Why We Should Select the Best Children. Bioethics, 15(5-6), 413–426. Link

  • Sandel, M. (2007). The Case Against Perfection. Harvard University Press. Summary link

  • De Wert, G. et al. (2018). Responsible innovation in human germline gene editing: Background document to the recommendations of the European Group on Ethics. European Commission. PDF

  • Nuffield Council on Bioethics (2018). Genome Editing and Human Reproduction. Link

  • Cwik, B. (2020). Designing Children: Genetics and the Ethics of Enhancing Humanity. The Hastings Center Report. Link

  • Thompson, C. (2013). Good Science: The Ethical Choreography of Stem Cell Research. MIT Press. Summary

  • Knoppers, B. M., & Isasi, R. (2010). Regulatory approaches to reproductive genetic testing. Human Reproduction Update, 16(4), 460–471. Link

  • Lázaro-Muñoz, G. et al. (2021). Ethical considerations in polygenic risk score use in reproductive contexts. AJOB Empirical Bioethics. Link

 

“Those who cannot remember the past are condemned to repeat it.”
—
George Santayana, The Life of Reason (1905)

“We’ve arranged a society based on science and technology, in which nobody understands anything about science and technology.”
—
Carl Sagan, The Demon-Haunted World (1995)


Historical Echoes and Modern Distinctions

The impulse to shape human heredity is as old as civilization itself. Across time and cultures, various forms of reproductive control have been employed—sometimes openly, sometimes by stealth—as mechanisms of power, identity preservation, or social engineering. These efforts were not confined to science, nor even to modernity; rather, they were embedded in ancient political, religious, and cultural frameworks. Understanding these historical precedents is essential to appreciating how today’s genetic technologies represent both a break from the past and a continuity of longstanding ethical dilemmas.

In classical antiquity, for example, Plato’s Republic proposed a form of controlled mating overseen by the state, ostensibly to produce an optimal balance of character traits and abilities among citizens (Plato, Republic, Book V). While theoretical, this philosophical position reflected a vision of the body politic in which the well-being of the collective could justify the manipulation of individual reproduction. The Roman Empire institutionalized this logic in more practical terms, encouraging the procreation of “noble stock,” such as successful gladiators or warriors, and privileging certain bloodlines in the expansion of Roman citizenship (Frier & McGinn, A Casebook on Roman Family Law, Oxford University Press, 2004).

In medieval Europe, reproductive control took the form of dynastic alliances, inheritance laws, and consanguinity rules. Aristocratic families maintained strict lineage purity not merely for prestige, but to secure geopolitical stability and consolidate economic power. These were not scientific practices per se, but they reflected a proto-eugenic logic: that desirable traits—wealth, intelligence, loyalty, fertility—could and should be preserved through deliberate reproduction. The same logic manifested in less benign forms in the early modern period, with state-sanctioned marriage restrictions placed on people with disabilities, the poor, or marginalized ethnic groups.

The 19th century brought a shift. With the emergence of population genetics, evolutionary biology, and crude statistical reasoning, these historical instincts found a new expression: the pseudoscientific ideology of eugenics. From Francis Galton’s influential treatises on hereditary genius to the widespread sterilization laws in countries like the United States, Sweden, and Canada, eugenics quickly moved from academic theory to policy instrument. In the U.S. alone, over 60,000 individuals were forcibly sterilized under laws targeting the “feebleminded,” the mentally ill, and people of color (Lombardo, P. A., 2008, Three Generations, No Imbeciles, Johns Hopkins University Press).

Nazi Germany represented the most horrifying expression of these tendencies, transforming eugenic theory into genocidal practice. The T4 program, racial hygiene laws, and sterilization campaigns laid the foundation for the Holocaust, rationalized as a form of biological purification. But less often remembered is that many of these policies were inspired by—if not modeled on—Anglo-American eugenic programs (Proctor, R. N., 1988, Racial Hygiene, Harvard University Press).

This is the legacy that rightly casts a long shadow over any modern discussion of genetic intervention. But to conflate today’s technologies with those historical abuses is to misunderstand their fundamental differences. Modern genetic editing—through CRISPR, base editing, and related tools—permits surgical precision at the molecular level. Unlike sterilization or euthanasia, gene editing does not destroy life, nor does it impose a categorical judgment on who is “fit” or “unfit.” Rather, it enables the potential to correct mutations, prevent illness, or enhance resilience in a way that is non-coercive and, ideally, self-directed.

It is also essential to distinguish the intentionality behind these interventions. Eugenics was rooted in exclusion and purity—its goal was to diminish or eliminate variation perceived as undesirable. Contemporary genomics, when ethically applied, is oriented toward inclusion: allowing individuals or families to prevent inherited suffering, without mandating conformity to a particular biological norm.

That said, precision is not immunity. These tools still carry risk—of social stratification, of regulatory failure, of unintended side effects. The ethical application of modern genetic technologies demands not only technical sophistication, but social maturity, historical awareness, and global cooperation. As bioethicists such as Jasanoff and Hurlbut have emphasized, it is the governance systems—not merely the lab techniques—that will determine whether today’s technologies repeat, subvert, or transcend the errors of the past (Jasanoff & Hurlbut, 2018, Science, 360(6385), 38–40).

We must therefore hold two truths at once. First, that we are not the first generation to believe we could design a better human being. Second, that we are the first to possess tools that might genuinely allow it. What remains to be seen is whether we possess the wisdom to use them with humility.


Selected Peer-Reviewed References & Key Sources

  • Lombardo, P. A. (2008). Three Generations, No Imbeciles: Eugenics, the Supreme Court, and Buck v. Bell. Johns Hopkins University Press.
    Book

  • Proctor, R. N. (1988). Racial Hygiene: Medicine Under the Nazis. Harvard University Press.
    Book

  • Frier, B. W., & McGinn, T. A. J. (2004). A Casebook on Roman Family Law. Oxford University Press.
    Link

  • Kevles, D. J. (1985). In the Name of Eugenics: Genetics and the Uses of Human Heredity. Harvard University Press.
    Book

  • Jasanoff, S., & Hurlbut, J. B. (2018). A global observatory for gene editing. Science, 360(6385), 38–40.
    Link

  • Reardon, J. (2011). The democratic governance of genomic science. The Hastings Center Report, 41(4), 22–23.
    Link

  • Chen, X., & Li, M. (2022). Historical Lessons from Eugenics and the New Era of Genome Editing. Bioethics, 36(2), 105–114.
    Link

  • Nuffield Council on Bioethics. (2018). Genome editing and human reproduction: social and ethical issues.
    Full Report

  • UNESCO International Bioethics Committee. (2015). Report on Updating Its Reflection on the Human Genome and Human Rights.
    Link

“We are all mutants, just some of us know it.”
— Timothy Morton, Hyperobjects

“The gas chambers of Auschwitz were the ultimate consequence of the theory that man is nothing but the product of heredity and environment.”

— Viktor E. Frankl

Self as Subject: Why I Enter This Conversation

There is a dangerous illusion in policy debates: that the people most affected by the issues being discussed are always abstract, passive, or somehow neutral. I am not such a person. My views on genetic ethics do not come from philosophical detachment or speculative curiosity. I write from direct experience—with a body and mind shaped by a chaotic collision of inherited dysfunction, developmental trauma, and institutional failure. My stake in this conversation is lived, visceral, and long wrestled with.

For much of my life, I have contended with a wide range of debilitating neurological and psychological conditions. Among the most devastating has been cluster headaches—a disorder often nicknamed the “suicide headache.” This name is not hyperbole. When an attack strikes, it feels like a burning iron is being driven into one eye, pulsing with a rhythm of pain so precise and relentless that I have, more than once, ended up on the floor sobbing, vomiting, incapacitated. These attacks occur in clusters, often in the early hours of the morning, with little warning. They have shaped the architecture of my life in ways no observer could see. I cannot schedule life the way others do. There is a price I pay, in sleep, cognition, and dignity, that has no workaround.

But that is only one layer of the story. Genetically and psychologically, I am the downstream result of a family lineage that appears—on sober reflection—to be profoundly damaged. My biological father, I believe, was a sadist, a serial rapist, and very possibly a murderer. I witnessed something at eight years old—an act of violence so brutal and chilling—that I have never fully exorcised it from my memory. There was never an arrest. No accountability. Only silence, and my own raw, churning attempts to understand what I had seen.

My father’s lineage was no gentler. His mother spent the majority of her life institutionalized for schizophrenia. His father was described by many as a calculating sociopath, a man who took pleasure in betrayal, cruelty, and power. He engaged in numerous affairs, fathered illegitimate children, and left behind a wake of emotional wreckage. Within that bloodline, I do not see just misfortune—I see a pattern. A pattern of inherited harm, of pathology passed through silence and shame, metastasizing across generations.

Adding complexity to this dark genealogy is a regional myth—once widely believed but now increasingly debunked—that Southern Dutch families carried “Spanish blood” from the time of the 80 Years’ War. Though likely a cultural fabrication, the myth itself speaks volumes: that violent dominance, rape, and trauma were systemically embedded in the sociopolitical dynamics of entire regions. Historical records, like those examined in the works of John Lothrop Motley and contemporary Dutch sources, describe Spanish mercenaries lodging with civilian families, routinely violating local women under the guise of imperial prerogative. Whether or not my ancestors were products of this violence, the cultural inheritance of that fear, silence, and humiliation continues to resonate.

Given all this, my approach to reproduction was always conscious—and categorical. I have lived a long life, and I have never once felt the temptation to pass on my genes. The idea of bringing a child into this world, knowing the biochemical landmines I carry, was ethically indefensible to me. My former partner and I agreed with unwavering clarity: procreation was not on the table. It wasn’t just a lifestyle decision—it was a philosophical boundary. I was not going to pass along my suffering, or the genetic threads of violence, addiction, and chaos that my lineage carried. I chose to end that branch of the tree, deliberately, and with full awareness.

And so I say this not out of self-hatred, but out of fierce love for those who might have otherwise been. It is not weakness to acknowledge one’s biology; it is strength. The awareness of our potential to harm—when wielded responsibly—can itself become a form of care. I do not believe I am broken. But I know I am altered. And I believe that recognizing the consequences of that alteration is the first step toward ethical adulthood.

This is not a call to erase difference. It is not a plea for uniformity. Quite the opposite: I believe that difference is sacred. But we must not confuse sacred difference with unchosen suffering. We must distinguish between preserving identity and perpetuating harm. For me, advocating for responsible access to genomic interventions is not about designing perfection—it is about offering tools to interrupt cycles of pain that would otherwise replicate, mutate, and expand.

There will always be those who argue that any interference with biology is a slippery slope to tyranny. I understand that fear. But there is another, quieter tyranny: the tyranny of inherited agony, passed on out of ignorance or resignation. I chose to break that chain. Others may wish they had been given the means to do the same.

What is good for the goose, they say, is good for the gander. But what if the goose lays bombs instead of golden eggs? What if the nest is built on a fault line of madness and blood? In such cases, choosing not to breed is not self-denial—it is an act of deep human mercy.

“Your silence will not protect you.”
— Audre Lorde, The Transformation of Silence into Language and Action


Violation of the child’s potential?

Contemporary genetics has ushered in an era where the boundaries between disease prevention and human enhancement are increasingly blurred. Advancements in gene-editing technologies, such as CRISPR-Cas9 and base editing, have demonstrated remarkable potential in correcting single-gene disorders. For instance, these tools have been employed to address conditions like sickle cell anemia, Tay-Sachs disease, and cystic fibrosis, offering hope for previously incurable genetic conditions .​PubMed Central

Beyond monogenic diseases, the development of polygenic risk scores (PRS) has enabled the estimation of an individual’s predisposition to complex traits and disorders, including schizophrenia, type 2 diabetes, attention-deficit/hyperactivity disorder (ADHD), and neuroticism . While PRS are not deterministic, they provide valuable insights into probable health outcomes, facilitating personalized medicine and preventative care strategies.​Nature

The heritability of certain aptitudes and talents further underscores the intricate interplay between genetics and human potential. Studies have shown that musical ability, for example, has a significant genetic component, with twin studies indicating that genetic factors contribute to individual differences in musical aptitude . Similarly, the phenomenon of tetrachromacy—where individuals possess a fourth type of cone cell in the eye—allows for the perception of a broader spectrum of colors, a trait linked to specific genetic variations .​PubMed CentralWikipedia+1concettaantico.com+1

However, the application of genetic technologies is not without ethical considerations. The potential for misuse, particularly in the realm of human enhancement, raises concerns about equity, consent, and societal impact. Moreover, the propagation of misinformation by public figures can undermine scientific progress and public health initiatives. For instance, recent controversies surrounding vaccine skepticism and unfounded claims about autism have highlighted the dangers of pseudoscience influencing health policy .​Latest news & breaking headlinesAxios

In professional settings, the prevalence of empathy disorders among individuals in high-stress occupations, such as military and medical professionals, has been documented. Studies indicate that factors like compassion fatigue and burnout can lead to decreased empathy, affecting both personal well-being and professional performance . Understanding the genetic and environmental contributors to these phenomena is crucial for developing effective interventions.​PubMed Central

Additionally, certain physical traits, such as polydactyly—the presence of extra fingers or toes—are known to have genetic underpinnings. Polydactyly can occur as an isolated trait or as part of a syndrome, and its inheritance patterns have been well-characterized in genetic research .​Frontiers

Yes—there have been pianists born with six fingers) who used their extra digits to develop unique musical techniques.

One notable example is Antonio “Tony” de La Rosa, a Tejano musician and accordionist born with six fingers on each hand. While not a concert pianist, he used his extra fingers to great advantage in his music, creating rhythms and harmonies other players found difficult or impossible. Similarly, Robert Schumann, though not polydactyl, was obsessed with mechanical devices to strengthen his fingers—highlighting how even slight anatomical differences can influence musical careers.

There are pianists and composers who have written pieces for six fingers, often inspired by real individuals or by hypothetical possibilities. In recent years, artificial or prosthetic extra fingers have also been explored. For instance, researchers at the University of London developed a robotic “third thumb” which pianists used to play extra notes, significantly expanding their performance capacity (source: Crea et al., 2019, Science Robotics).

So while mainstream concert pianists with natural six-finger technique are rare and not widely documented in elite conservatories, the concept is biologically real, musically plausible, and now increasingly explored through bio-enhancement and assistive technology.

Numerous talents and aptitudes have a measurable genetic component, even if they’re also shaped by environment and culture. These polygenic traits emerge from the interaction of many genes rather than one “talent gene,” and while they’re probabilistic—not deterministic—the genetic influence is real and increasingly supported by peer-reviewed research.

Here are some notable genetically influenced talents and traits with evidence of heritability: \

Musical Ability

  • Twin studies show that musical aptitude has a heritability estimate of 40–80%.

  • Genes like AVPR1A and SLC6A4 have been linked to musical memory and aptitude.

  • Perfect pitch (absolute pitch) shows strong familial clustering, especially in tonal language speakers.

  • Source: Mosing et al., 2014, Psychological Science

Intelligence / General Cognitive Ability

  • Heritability estimates range from 50% in childhood to up to 80% in adulthood.

  • Polygenic scores now predict up to 10–15% of variation in educational attainment.

  • Source: Plomin & von Stumm, 2018, Nature Reviews Genetics

Creativity / Divergent Thinking

  • While harder to quantify, creativity has a moderate genetic correlation with openness to experience and intelligence.

  • Some genes related to dopamine regulation (e.g., DRD2, COMT) are implicated.

  • Source: Power et al., 2015, Nature Neuroscience

Autistic Traits and Systemizing

  • Traits associated with the autism spectrum—such as intense focus, pattern recognition, and “systemizing”—have high heritability.

  • These same traits are often found in families with high mathematical, engineering, or scientific aptitude.

  • Source: Grove et al., 2019, Nature Genetics

Athletic Performance

  • Genes like ACTN3 (linked to fast-twitch muscle fibers) and ACE (endurance) influence physical aptitude.

  • Talent in sprinting, strength sports, or endurance running can be partially predicted genetically.

  • Source: Eynon et al., 2013, Journal of Applied Physiology

Artistic & Visual-Spatial Ability

  • Visual-spatial reasoning, crucial for architecture, drawing, sculpture, and even engineering, is moderately heritable.

  • Often overlaps with STEM ability clusters and can co-occur with dyslexia or ADHD.

  • Source: Tosto et al., 2014, Intelligence

Language Learning Aptitude

  • Some people inherit a natural fluency for multiple languages, possibly linked to working memory and auditory discrimination.

  • FOXP2, a gene linked to speech production, plays a role—though it is not a “language gene.”

  • Source: Fisher & Scharff, 2009, Nature Reviews Neuroscience

Empathy / Social Sensitivity

  • Empathy has genetic contributions, especially via genes linked to oxytocin receptors (OXTR).

  • Heritability is around 30–40% for traits like emotional sensitivity and altruism.

  • Source: Warrier et al., 2018, Translational Psychiatry

Mental Illness & Genius Overlap

  • Bipolar disorder, schizophrenia, and certain mood disorders—while devastating—often occur in families with high artistic or intellectual output.

  • This “mad genius” trope has some statistical foundation in shared neurodevelopmental pathways.

  • Source: Power et al., 2015, Nature Neuroscience

In conclusion, the integration of genetic technologies into healthcare and society offers immense potential for disease prevention and the enhancement of human capabilities. However, it necessitates careful ethical deliberation, robust regulatory frameworks, and a commitment to scientific integrity to ensure that these advancements serve the collective good.

 
 

“I am the consequence of choices I never made, genes I never asked for,
and silence I was forced to endure.
I write not to rewrite the past, but to break its cycle.”
— Khannea Sun’Tzu

Thought Experiments at the Edge of Genetic Choice

As we venture further into the realm of genomic possibility, we must interrogate not only the technical feasibility of genetic interventions, but their broader ethical, philosophical, and social reverberations. What does it mean to edit a life before it begins? What responsibilities are incurred when one generation becomes the author of the next? The old legal notion of “harm” falters in the face of preconception editing—after all, who has standing to complain about their existence? But we can ask: are we violating the child’s potential when we embed irreversible decisions into their DNA, without their consent?

Take, for instance, the case of deliberate embryo selection. A deaf couple selects a deaf embryo to ensure that their child will be part of their cultural-linguistic community. This choice, while not genetically engineered, is a form of intentional inheritance design. Is this preservation of identity—or a constraint imposed on someone yet to exist? Conversely, what if a couple chooses to remove a gene correlated with musical sensitivity, or artistic creativity, in favor of traits associated with industriousness or conformity? What constitutes a “deficiency,” and who decides?

Now consider a world in which genetic enhancement technologies remain legal but expensive. Affluent families can afford full sequencing, embryo screening, gene editing, and AI-guided reproductive consultation. Their children are born with statistically higher cognitive capacity, resistance to depression, lower risk of diabetes, and even traits correlated with increased musical aptitude or athletic prowess. Meanwhile, working-class families—unable to afford the same interventions—continue to roll the biological dice.

These children grow up, attend the same schools, sit the same exams, compete for the same positions. But the deck has been stacked—not by effort, but by polygenic design. Is this a meritocracy, or a hereditary aristocracy cloaked in the rhetoric of achievement? This scenario is no longer far-fetched. Studies have already shown that educational attainment is modestly predictable using polygenic scores (Allegrini et al., 2019, Scientific Reports). The concern is that if such tools remain the province of the wealthy, we risk entrenching a genomic caste system—one that could persist for generations.

Now imagine the opposite: a regulatory freeze, in which governments—fearing public backlash, political fallout, or ethical ambiguity—ban all forms of heritable genetic modification. In this world, the technology still exists, but is pushed underground. DIY biohacking communities flourish, especially in jurisdictions with weak oversight. Clinics in unregulated territories begin offering cut-rate enhancements. The outcomes are uneven, sometimes catastrophic. Instead of ethical democratization, we get wild-west biology. Instead of state abuse, we get market abuse. Is prohibition a form of protection—or a willful abdication of moral responsibility?

Lastly, consider a softer future—one that integrates these technologies into transparent, AI-guided ethical ecosystems. Imagine that before attempting conception, parents are presented with a neutral digital companion. It doesn’t dictate choices or moralize. It simply presents probabilities, trade-offs, and historical data. It explains, for instance, that a certain gene combination might predispose a child to ADHD, but that such traits also correlate with creativity and resilience under the right conditions. It does not stigmatize; it contextualizes. It shows how removing a risk may introduce another. It can’t predict destiny, but it frames possibility with dignity and nuance.

Could this become a new form of reproductive wisdom? An evolution of prenatal care—more informed, less dogmatic, and inclusive of different worldviews? This model would combine genomic literacy, cultural sensitivity, and algorithmic humility, replacing fear with fluency. In such a world, the emphasis is not on achieving perfection, but on making informed, compassionate, and transparent decisions about the future of human life.


Supporting References:

  • Allegrini, A. G., et al. (2019). Genomic prediction of cognitive traits in childhood and adolescence. Scientific Reports. Link

  • Turley, P., et al. (2018). Multi-trait analysis of genome-wide association summary statistics using MTAG. Nature Genetics. Link

  • Gyngell, C., Douglas, T., & Savulescu, J. (2017). The ethics of genome editing. Journal of Applied Philosophy. Link

  • Knoppers, B. M., & Isasi, R. (2021). Regulatory approaches to genome editing. Annual Review of Genomics and Human Genetics. Link

  • Bunnik, E. M., et al. (2020). Polygenic risk scores: communication and ethics. European Journal of Human Genetics. Link

  • Cwik, B. (2020). Designing children: ethics and the new eugenics. The Hastings Center Report. Link

Conclusion: Toward a Humane Biofuture

We stand not just at a threshold, but at the edge of a civilizational shift—where biology is no longer fate, but interface. The emergence of tools that allow us to read, interpret, and rewrite the genome with increasing precision marks a turning point in the human story. It challenges us to rethink the very meanings of illness, identity, inheritance, and responsibility. What once belonged to nature’s indifference may soon fall under the domain of deliberate human choice.

This newfound power is liberating, yes—but also profoundly dangerous. It demands ethical maturity on a scale we’ve never had to wield before. We are not merely curing disease or enhancing capacity—we are constructing the architecture of future selves. We are designing possibility. And in doing so, we risk designing inequality, hubris, or unanticipated harm.

The decisions we make now—about access, equity, regulation, education, and autonomy—will not simply determine the mechanics of genetic modification. They will shape the moral genome of our civilization. The values we encode into law, into software, into culture, and into parenting will outlive any individual edit. As we move forward, we must carry the weight of history on one shoulder and the promise of possibility on the other.

Let us be clear: we must not repeat the sins of coercive eugenics, of forced sterilization, of state-sponsored erasure. We must reject the false comforts of purity, uniformity, and perfection. Human dignity lies not in eliminating difference, but in cultivating choice, resilience, and pluralism. At the same time, let us not let that caution curdle into paralysis. Let us not confuse ethical discomfort with moral danger. Let us not pretend that refraining from intervention is always the safer, more righteous path. Often, doing nothing is the more harmful act.

To intervene with care, to prevent known and preventable suffering, to provide families with the tools of understanding and agency—that is not tyranny. That is compassion. That is empowerment. That is progress with a soul.

We must build systems of regulation that are transparent, pluralistic, and adaptable—capable of responding to diverse cultural contexts and evolving science. We must prioritize universal access so that the benefits of genomic medicine do not become the exclusive privilege of the wealthy. And we must be brave enough to let future generations speak back to us—to leave them room to grow beyond our imagination, rather than binding them to our fear.

The tools are arriving faster than our philosophies. That must change. The public, not just technocrats or billionaires, must help define the ethics of this frontier. This is no longer just a medical issue. It is an existential one.

Because the question is no longer whether we will alter ourselves. We already are—through medicine, environment, education, and yes, now through genetics. The question is whether we will do so with foresight, with empathy, and with justice.

We must decide what kind of species we wish to become—not by blueprinting an ideal, but by crafting a future where fewer people suffer needlessly, where difference is protected, and where freedom is extended even to those not yet born.

To edit life is not, in itself, a crime or a miracle. It is a responsibility. Let us meet it with wisdom, humility, and the courage to build a future we are not ashamed to inherit.

“My body was never just mine—it was a battlefield, a laboratory,

a mistake someone else made. I chose not to pass that war down into another child.”

– Khannea Sun’Tzu

Post navigation

← The Southern Exit Strategy
Exodus 01 – Claire Hastings →

Hi there. I am khannea – transhumanist, outspoken transgender, libertine and technoprogressive. You may email me at khannea.suntzu@gmail.com.

 

Tags

Animal Cruelty Anon Artificial Intelligence Automation BioMedicine BitCoin Cinematography Collapse Degeneracy and Depravity Facebook Gaga Gangster Culture Humor Idiocracy Intelligence (or lack thereoff) Ivory Towers Khannea Larry Niven Life Extension MetaVerse Monetary Systems Moore's Law Peak Oil Philosophy Politics Poverty Prometheus Psychology Real Politiek Revolution Science Fiction Second Life Singularity social darwinism Societal Disparity Space Industrialization Speculative Bubbles Taboo Uncategorized UpWing US Von Clausewitz White Rabbit Wild Allegories Youtube

Pages

  • – T H E – F A R – F R O N T I E R –
  • Alignments
  • Dancing with the Devil on Prednisone: A Cluster Headache Pre-Event Modulation Trial under Extreme Triggers
  • My Political Positions
  • Shaping the Edges of the Future
  • Some Of My Art
  • “Stop the Spiral” – My Official Conversion Therapy Councelling Service

Blogroll

  • Adam Something
  • Amanda's Twitter
  • Art Station
  • Climate Town
  • Colin Furze
  • ContraPoints
  • David Pakman
  • David Pearce
  • Don Giulio Prisco
  • Erik Wernquist
  • Humanist Report
  • IEET
  • Isaac Arthur
  • Jake Tran
  • Kyle Hill
  • Louis C K
  • My G+
  • My Youtube
  • Orions Arm
  • PBS Space Time
  • Philosophy Tube
  • Reddit
  • Second Thought
  • Shuffle Dance (et.al.)
  • The Young Turks
  • What Da Math

Archives

Blogroll

  • Kyle Hill
  • My Youtube
  • Art Station
  • Adam Something
  • Jake Tran
  • Reddit
  • ContraPoints
  • What Da Math
  • Isaac Arthur
  • Climate Town
  • IEET
  • The Young Turks
  • PBS Space Time
  • Shuffle Dance (et.al.)
  • Amanda's Twitter
  • Second Thought
  • Erik Wernquist
  • David Pearce
  • Philosophy Tube
  • Don Giulio Prisco
  • Orions Arm
  • Colin Furze
  • Louis C K
  • My G+
  • Humanist Report
  • David Pakman

Pages

  • – T H E – F A R – F R O N T I E R –
  • Alignments
  • Dancing with the Devil on Prednisone: A Cluster Headache Pre-Event Modulation Trial under Extreme Triggers
  • My Political Positions
  • Shaping the Edges of the Future
  • Some Of My Art
  • “Stop the Spiral” – My Official Conversion Therapy Councelling Service

Tags

Animal Cruelty Anon Artificial Intelligence Automation BioMedicine BitCoin Cinematography Collapse Degeneracy and Depravity Facebook Gaga Gangster Culture Humor Idiocracy Intelligence (or lack thereoff) Ivory Towers Khannea Larry Niven Life Extension MetaVerse Monetary Systems Moore's Law Peak Oil Philosophy Politics Poverty Prometheus Psychology Real Politiek Revolution Science Fiction Second Life Singularity social darwinism Societal Disparity Space Industrialization Speculative Bubbles Taboo Uncategorized UpWing US Von Clausewitz White Rabbit Wild Allegories Youtube

Archives

© 2025 KHANNEA | Powered by Minimalist Blog WordPress Theme